"Don't for heaven's sake, be afraid of talking nonsense! But you must pay attention to your nonsense." —Ludwig Wittgenstein, "Culture and Value" p.59.
I am sure I have often said and have certainly often
heard others say: "I didn't realise until afterwards, what I was trying to
do." This post is an attempt to pay close attention to the nonsense buried
in this utterance and to tentatively suggest that the associated notion of
unconscious striving — of unconscious desire even — is incoherent. It may
already be clear that such a view runs contrary to one or two foundational
ideas within psychoanalysis, some of which continue to garner significant
recognition within the arts. If we shouldn't be afraid of talking nonsense,
then we probably shouldn't be afraid of identifying nonsense either.
To realise something after the fact is to have
learned something new; to have become aware of something that was previously
unclear or inaccessible. The sentence "I didn't realise until afterwards,
what I was trying to do." is commonly used as an acknowledgement that our
goals are often vague, fragmentary or imprecise and only through the gradual,
or sometimes sudden, accumulation of understanding do we become capable of clearly
articulating this more developed knowledge. But whilst our goals can be sketchy,
a vague intention is not an intention for vague outcome. A sketchy idea for a diagram
is rarely a desire for a sketchy diagram.
There is nothing confused or paradoxical about such
thoughts. Where the confusion arises is in the suggestion that some part of us,
some inner and inaccessible intelligence, seeks to express itself through our
actions; that an alleged unconscious or subconscious self is trying to tell us things that may only
dawn upon our conscious awareness later. Certainly there are times when we
recognise patterns or significances in our past actions. But is this sufficient
grounds for the supposition that we are host to unconscious intentions that are
striving to articulate themselves? I hope to show that it is not.
Trying, striving, endeavouring, pursuing, envisaging,
seeking, aiming etc. are intentional goal orientated behaviours. Without goals
there can be no striving because there
can be nothing to strive towards. If we were never capable of communicating an outcome of our actions in any shape or form, then we could not be said to try to achieve something either. "All 'willing' is willing something," as the neurologist
Oliver Sacks puts it.
If someone asks us what we are doing and we have no
answer, then we cannot be said to be acting purposefully. It is for this reason
that goals are fundamentally reliant upon our powers of communication; upon our
ability to offer some sort of token, word or gesture that would be acceptable
to others as a representation of our intention.
In a 2006 paper, Jack Glaser and John Kihlstrom argue
that: "Unconscious Volition Is Not an Oxymoron." They write:
...the unconscious, in addition to being a passive categorizer, evaluator, and semantic processor, has processing goals (for example, accuracy, egalitarianism) of its own, can be vigilant for threats to the attainment of these goals, and will proactively compensate for such threats.
Clearly Glaser and Kihlstrom recognise that volition
demands goals, but it is extraordinary that they are prepared to suggest that
unconscious behaviour is fundamentally intentional: that it has ulterior motives, even if these are as seemingly benign and basic as accuracy
and egalitarianism etc. In its most extreme form, such a view opens the door to
any number of unwitting intentions and renders us as nothing more than
witnesses to motives beyond our control or ken.
If goals can be pursued without our conscious awareness or control,
then we are puppets in a theatre not of our own making, and all we can do is
observe our actions like passive audience members in the hope of gleaning some
comprehension of the hidden goals that actually drive us. Consciousness never
looked more wretched.
The alternative is to reject the notion of
unconscious volition altogether and to seek a less extravagant explanation.
When in 1974 Oliver Sacks broke his leg whilst
fleeing from a bull, the trauma of the injury left him with a temporary
inability to properly sense or move his leg. In essence the episode had rid him of all knowhow in the use of his leg. A closely related condition is
sometimes experienced by people who become temporarily blind in response to the
traumatic loss of a loved one or some other major upset. These sorts of
psychological responses to trauma are known as "Conversion Disorders"
and it is interesting to note that the term was first coined by Freud as an
alternative to "hysteria" or "hysterical blindness."
In a paper on the subject of conversion disorders,
Harvey et al. (2006) point out that: "One difficulty facing research in
this field is the complexity of the conceptual issues and variable ways in
which terminology has been used." The authors helpfully include a table of
definitions and explanations of key terminology and they also explicitly state
that conversion disorders are “not intentionally produced” and cannot be feigned.
It should be made clear that they do not make any suggestion that conversion
disorders are the result of unconscious intention, striving, trying etc.
When overtired drivers are overcome by sleep, their
unconscious is not striving to take control. If you attempt to kill yourself by
holding your breath, it is not inner volition that will rob you of consciousness
before the job is done. These are simply highly evolved autonomic responses
that have no goals and do not have to strive, seek or endeavour to impose
themselves. They have no more volition than the iris of the eye. No doubt conversion
disorders are similarly rooted in complex autonomic processes.
Can we aim for one thing only to find that we were actually aiming for something else? If goals are necessarily communicable, then it follows that we cannot be oblivious of those we are pursuing. We can certainly aim for inappropriate goals or be confused, uncertain or vague about our goals, as I have already mentioned. But I don't think we can be mistaken that the thing we are intent upon is actually the thing we are intent upon. That would come at an extremely high price; the price of intention itself.
Can we aim for one thing only to find that we were actually aiming for something else? If goals are necessarily communicable, then it follows that we cannot be oblivious of those we are pursuing. We can certainly aim for inappropriate goals or be confused, uncertain or vague about our goals, as I have already mentioned. But I don't think we can be mistaken that the thing we are intent upon is actually the thing we are intent upon. That would come at an extremely high price; the price of intention itself.