Inasmuch
as institutions of education are devoted to various forms of evaluation and
assessment it seems logical that the research of art teachers should be assessed
just as that of other academics. If the professional practice of art teachers is
to be given comparable credence as other disciplines, and is to be
financially supported, then presumably art teachers should be able to demonstrate the
value of their output to the wider community – and the more significant the better.
Nonetheless, as a discipline, art does not fit comfortably within
the regime of research assessment (See REF), not least because of the continual emphasis on the very term
"research". Do artists conduct research? Does it make sense to define
the work that artists produce as research?
Most
people think of artists as practitioners, as makers, certainly not as bookish
academics or scholars lost amongst the shelves of a dusky archive and even less
as lab-coat-clad experimenters. But perhaps this is to make a caricature of
what is surely a heterogeneous practice in which many forms of enquiry are
engaged. Neither is it intended to suggest that artists do not concern themselves
with questions of knowledge or understanding. They do. But the search that
artists are involved with articulates itself primarily through a frequently messy
and unstructured engagement with materials and processes. Art concerns itself
with experience from the inside, as it were, and looks to knowledge as a means
to deepen this experience, much less as a means to understand it. In recent
times this form of enquiry has come to be called "Situated Knowledge"
or "Material Thinking" and it seems likely that these terms, and the
arguments that underpin them, have emerged as a backlash against the
preponderance of emphasis placed upon more conventional forms of knowledge
production that are so venerated by the Research Excellence Framework and its
like.
If
art creates knowledge at all it is certainly not because artists deliberately
seek it in the ways that, for example, scientists do. Artistic Method, if there
ever were such a thing, would doubtless be a singularly ineffective means to
accumulate knowledge or articulate it. Any knowledge that comes about through
the creation or interpretation of art does so as a by-product of experience -
experience that must first be felt and interpreted to be understood. Experience
is the point, both in the making and in the contemplative encounter with art,
even if the experience, as such, is the
discovery of knowledge. Art shows us how the experience of forming - as
distinct from 'acquiring' - knowledge can, in itself, be more edifying and
fulfilling than knowledge alone. Where art is concerned, experience eclipses
knowledge.
“It is better to make a
piece of music than to perform one, better to perform one than to listen to
one, better to listen to one than to misuse it as a means of distraction,
entertainment, or acquisition of ‘culture.’”
John
Cage does an excellent job here of clarifying the difference between various
kinds of involvement and how, as we remove ourselves further and further from
being 'in' an experience, the more passive and pointless the exercise. Art is
not a declarative process - it does not hand itself over easily. The power of
art resides in the degree to which it rewards concerted engagement. You have to
work at it and the closer you approach the condition of the maker - in fact of
supplanting them - the more rewarding the experience promises to be. At its
best, art transforms its audience, in the act of interpretation, into creators,
not viewers, not listeners, nor even performers, but makers: creators of significance.
There
are deep pleasures to be gained from this process: "The pleasure of finding things out" as physicist Richard
Feynman put it, not of being told, nor even of possessing new knowledge, but of
engaging to the point of discovery. Art is not simply something we consume
then, but rather something we make
anew for ourselves.
It
should be apparent by now that the skills, insights and imagination of the
artist are only fragments in the overall constitution of the artwork, though
indispensably important ones. But without the engagement of an audience the
artwork can be little more than an inert and anonymous object. Each engaged
audience, each thoughtful viewer, re-creates the artwork - the more they
devote, the more they are likely to reap.
But
if it is we who re-create the artwork, if its significance is largely of our
own making then why credit the artist at all? Moreover, if the significance of
an artwork is, to some indeterminate degree, a projection of its audience then
how can an accurate estimate of the contribution of the artist ever be formed?
This is a question for which no criteria - whether for the evaluation of art students
or art teachers - will ever provide a satisfactory answer.
The
impact of any experience emanates in multiple directions like ripples on an already
turbulent pond. Quite how the influence of any particular impact can be
assessed from the ensuing tumult is highly questionable. Granted, large impacts
create a measurable increase in overall activity but if Chaos Theory has taught
us anything it is that small events can sometimes have profound consequences.
Culture
is the product of collective activity and the ripples across its surface are a
complex interleaving of causes and effects. By singling out only the measurable
influences, not only do we vastly exaggerate their perceived significance, but we
also overlook the significance of a multitude of other constitutive, and
therefore vital, contributions. The outcome is a situation where those
individuals who are already successful reap yet more rewards, whilst the
untried, the speculative and the unpredictable are simply ignored, thus promoting
and perpetuating a culture of risk aversion, performativity and self-regard.
1 comments:
I can see exactly what you are aiming at and you hit the nail right on the head. Thanks for another insightful post Jim
Post a Comment