Imagination allows us to recall memories at will and to
recombine them, in whole or in part, with seeming infinite variety and to use
these new combinations to consider, anticipate and respond to possible future
events. Imagination is
arguably one of the most formidable cognitive tools we possess, one that is
surpassed only by consciousness itself, indeed consciousness may well be an
impossibility without imagination, since how otherwise could we form a sense of
self without the means to knit the many disparate fragments together?
It is
tempting to assume that imagination is a singular entity without which life
would be reduced to little more than a procession of behaviors bereft of all
dimension; a bland succession of preprogrammed or acquired responses. In this
conception of imagination its lack would leave us unable to envisage the future
nor to learn from the past. Dreams, hopes and aspirations would vanish, whilst
desire would be reduced to vague shadow of its current form, plaguing us only
in the very moment of encounter with a desirable “object”. Without the means to
dwell on our desires we would be mercifully free of that all-to-human agony
arising from the expectation of future pain or misfortune, of anxieties played
and replayed interminably in the mind’s eye until the moment of reckoning and
enlarged beyond all measure in the process. Disappointment too would be
unthinkable as would all plans, intentions, failures and successes. But, as it
turns out, imagination does not emanate from a single neurological source nor
does it suffer total degradation when any one of it’s constituent elements is
impeded or damaged.
It is
often reported that children on the autistic spectrum lack imagination but,
once again, this claim betrays a limited understanding of the nature of
imagination (and autism for that matter). As the term “spectrum” would suggest,
autism involves a wide gamut of abilities from severe and wide ranging deficits
to near normal and even exceptional ability in specific areas. In fact, scientists
at King’s College London have recently concluded that about one third of
autistic males have “some form of outstanding ability compared with 19 per cent of females.”
Over the
last three decades psychologists like Uta Frith or Simon Baron-Cohen have
focused attention on what is termed “Theory of Mind” and its associated
deficits amongst autistic individuals. Theory of Mind - sometimes also known as
“social imagination” - describes the human ability to interpret other people’s
desires, beliefs and intentions: to form “metarepresentations” (mental
representations of other peoples’ mental representations). What is often
observed as a lack of symbolic or pretend play amongst autistic children for
instance - whilst previously taken as proof of their overall lack of
imagination – is now believed to be closely associated with these
characteristic difficulties of inferring and interpreting the thoughts and
intentions of others. Nonetheless, it is not uncommon for autistic children to
have other interests and skills that evidence imaginative engagement. This has
lead to speculation, that there may be discrete forms of imagination that are
called upon in different circumstances to overcome many of the obstacles that
constitute the complex fluctuating environments within which we commonly
operate.
If
imagination is the product of diverse mental processes, as is increasingly believed,
then it follows that different aspects of imagination draw upon a variety of
cognitive resources in different proportions and to different degrees. For example,
with individuals on the autism spectrum, whilst social imagination may be a
significant difficulty for many, varying degrees of difficulty with other forms
of imagination may also be present. Furthermore, it is by no means certain that
what appears as an instance of say Metaphoric Imagination in one situation
would of necessity harness the same cognitive resources in another. And if this
is the case, then the challenge of isolating the neurological basis of any
singular specific type of imagination could prove daunting if not impossible
for future scientific enquiry. However, whilst it is undoubtedly true that
imagination is a sophisticated process, the increasingly common tendency to
explain its functioning by recourse to ever more finely divided modules or
distributed networks may risk clouding the point. Whilst social imagination may
be implicated in the difficulties of
individuals on the autism spectrum it need not follow that the cause lies with
a discrete form of imagination. Just as likely is the possibility that the
imagination of individuals on the autism spectrum is perfectly intact but that their
cognitive predisposition towards social information and inference is in some
way impaired, inhibited or simply diminished.
Brain
science still has a lot to discover about the workings of the imagination, but
what is already clear is that definitions of imagination that describe it
simply as a variation on the
ability to form a representation (image, sound, feeling, etc) in the mind,
independent of any sensory stimulus are overly reductive and, as much of
the following discussion aims to show, may even turn out to be entirely wrong.
The closer we study the imagination the more it
turns out to be a tantalizingly elusive phenomenon; a complexity that continues
to tax the very brain networks that bring it into being. One of the most
challenging issues for theories and research into human imagination is the
question of what is known as “mental imagery”. Is it possible, for instance, that what we call mental imagery is nothing like images at all? Parts III & IV will explore
the history of this question in order to clarify some of the principal issues
that continue to generate considerable debate and disagreement on this subject.
0 comments:
Post a Comment