The
theory of the sign (Semiotics) is perhaps most closely associated with the work
of the Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure and the American philosopher
Charles Sanders Peirce. Over the last century, semiotics has had a very significant
influence in numerous fields of research from the arts and literary criticism
to biology and cognitive neuroscience. This post is intended to expose what I
think is a major flaw in the theory of the sign, a flaw that continues to
beleaguer scientific research and philosophical enquiry often in quite far
reaching ways.
The
Wikipedia entry on signs distinguishes between “natural” signs (or what Peirce
called “indexical signs”) and “conventional” signs (“symbols”). In an
influential paper from 1955 H. P. Grice makes a similar distinction between
what he calls "natural" and "non-natural" meanings. Grice's
distinction can therefore be seen in the same light that I aim to shed upon the
concept of natural signs.
On
the subject of the sign, Wikipedia states: “A natural sign bears a causal
relation to its object—for instance, thunder is a sign of storm, or medical
symptoms signify a disease.” I hope it is already evident that something isn't
quite right about this formulation. Symptoms are caused by disease but they are
not signals produced by disease. Likewise, thunder is caused by storms but its
influence upon the world is not a consequence of its possible status as a sign.
Such a status is not a property of thunder but can only be ascribed to the
sound of thunder in much the same way that the function of a tool is assigned
to it through use. This is not to suggest that nonverbal creatures cannot be
influenced by regularly occurring states of affairs and develop efficacious
responses as a consequence. But what I do want to suggest is that Pavlov’s
dogs, for example, did not salivate because they interpreted the bell as a sign
for dinner but because they had developed an autonomic response to the sound of
the bell. Autonomic responses do not function by way of interpretation,
unconscious or otherwise. Such a suggestion would undermine the important
distinction we typically assume between intentional behaviours (actions) and
the many non-conscious processes and responses that support, enable and
propagate the vast majority of life on Earth.
Discussing
C.S. Peirce's theory of the sign, Noble and Davidson (1996) state: "A
mouse rustling in the undergrowth is producing an indexical acoustic sign of
itself." If this is true, then every effect would have to be a sign of its
cause and the entire universe must be a teeming mass of communicating representations. According to Semetsky (2005 p.232) this is
precisely what Peirce believed: “Everything is a sign: the whole universe, for
Peirce, is perfused with signs.” Interestingly, Semetsky also identifies a paradox in Peirce’s
thinking since he also claimed that: “nothing is a sign unless it is
interpreted as a sign.” Indeed it should be obvious that the universe is only
composed of signs to the extent that we sign users are capable of interpreting
it as such. So when someone states: "A footprint... can communicate a message." this is either just a handy metaphor or the attribution of communicative agency where none is warranted. Such marks are interpretable
by someone capable of extrapolating from them in causal terms, but without a skilled
interpreter—moreover a symbol user capable of making meaningful attributions — the
marks are merely whatever they are: a cluster of properties. Interpretable things are not
communicators, but become interpretable only by being treated
as if they are part of practices of use — most commonly as part of practices of communication. Treating things in this way has significant predictive and retrodictive efficacy, so much so in fact, that we regularly
assume (mistakenly of course) that all life must be capable of the same skills of attribution.
An
advocate of semiotics might wish to interject here by denying that natural
signs are representations at all. This is the move that biosemiotician,
Marcello Barbieri (2013) makes when he claims that a natural sign “cannot show
or inform, it can only point to an object as if to say: ‘There it is!’” But
this is misconceived. What is pointing after all if not a form of showing?
Pointing is precisely equivalent to holding something up, presenting it or
nodding towards it. Likewise, if nothing is pointed to or shown when we exclaim
“There it is!” the utterance is unintelligible. Barbieri continues: “A
thermometer and a footprint are natural indices.” The suggestion that a
sophisticated instrument of numerical (i.e. symbolic) measurement is a natural
sign is simply absurd. But it gets worse. Barbieri claims:
Any metabolic process presupposes a goal directed organism and as such it is a semiotic process, since the organism selects and evaluates environmental stimuli with respect to their adequacy or inadequacy for the purpose of the organism’s survival. (2013)
Barbieri
is by no means alone in the attribution of goal directed action to the most
simple of forms of life:
The discovery and use of natural signs is a required prerequisite of existence for any living system because they are indispensable to movement, the search for food, regulation, communication, and many other information-related activities. (Sukhoverkhov 2012)
Sukhoverkhov
and Barbieri evidently agree that even the most simple organisms necessarily treat the world as if it were composed of signs that they use to direct their
behaviour. More astonishingly still, Peirce agrees: “The microscopist looks to
see whether the motions of a little creature show any purpose. If so, there is
mind there.” On this view then, not only is the universe perfused with signs,
but all life is perfused with mind.
The
assumption that mind is a prerequisite for any living system should be rejected
as both implausible and wildly extravagant. And the conclusion drawn by Peirce
on the basis of the movements of a microorganism is in obvious need of
revision. The point of error lies in the unjustified assumption that efficacious
movements constitute purposeful (i.e. goal directed) behaviour: actions.
If
the most simple organisms require minds to survive and propagate then there can
be no explanation of how mindedness could ever have evolved. A scientifically
parsimonious explanation of the evolution of intelligent life must therefore distinguish
between efficacious behaviour on the one hand and its more highly evolved
and genuinely purposeful cousin (action) on the other. When a microorganism
moves along a food gradient it is not propelled by a goal; it is propelled by
the causal influence of the food gradient. This sophisticated but nonetheless
predictable behaviour has been honed by millions of years of evolution in which
innumerable less well adapted creatures have perished. And whilst this
behaviour may resemble action, one thing should be certain: microorganisms are
not capable of producing representations of any sort, let alone goals.
There
is nothing natural about so called “natural signs”. Nor is interpretation a prerequisite
of life on Earth. Sensory discrimination is certainly a prerequisite of all life,
but it is certainly not a sign of
mind, not even incipient or rudimentary mind.
If
we want to understand the evolutionary emergence of mindedness, we first need
to be clear about what it takes for a creature to treat an object as if it has
properties that it does not actually possess. Such skills are certainly not to
be found amongst microorganisms. Mind is born of culture.
In the case of non-linguistic signs there is always the danger that their meanings will seem natural; one must view them with a certain detachment to see that their meanings are in fact the products of a culture, the result of shared assumptions and conventions. But in the case of linguistic signs the conventional or ‘arbitrary’ basis is obvious, and therefore by taking linguistics as a model one may avoid the familiar mistake of assuming that signs which appear natural to those who use them have an intrinsic meaning and require no explanation. (Culler 1975, p.6)
2 comments:
Excellent!
Thanks John, that means a lot to me.
Post a Comment