This literature review is intended as a brief
outline of the principal works and theorists currently pursuing non-representational approaches to the theorisation of cognition/mind. Since many
of the theorists listed have already been mentioned on his blog, I have provided links to this material where relevant.
Although the interest in non-representational theories of mind is clearly growing, the academic literature published is relatively sparse when compared with the material published on representational theories. Many of the papers, chapters and books gathered here centre around or are informed by discussions of previously published material in both the Analytic and Continental traditions of philosophy; Gilbert Ryle (1949) and Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1945) being commonly cited forerunners. American Pragmatism has also exerted a notable influence – see, for example, the work of Timor Solymosi (2013 & 2014), who makes frequent reference to the philosophy of John Dewey. Likewise, Eric P. Charles (2011) draws upon the work of both William James and Edwin Holt to develop a “New Realism” in psychology that dispenses with any explanatory reliance upon inner representations.
Although the interest in non-representational theories of mind is clearly growing, the academic literature published is relatively sparse when compared with the material published on representational theories. Many of the papers, chapters and books gathered here centre around or are informed by discussions of previously published material in both the Analytic and Continental traditions of philosophy; Gilbert Ryle (1949) and Maurice Merleau-Ponty (1945) being commonly cited forerunners. American Pragmatism has also exerted a notable influence – see, for example, the work of Timor Solymosi (2013 & 2014), who makes frequent reference to the philosophy of John Dewey. Likewise, Eric P. Charles (2011) draws upon the work of both William James and Edwin Holt to develop a “New Realism” in psychology that dispenses with any explanatory reliance upon inner representations.
Psychologists
Andrew D. Wilson and Sabrina Golonka (2013) take the influential work of J.J.
Gibson (1986) as a starting point for their exploration
of perception via his concept of “affordances”. They argue that embodied cognition
is the most “exciting hypothesis” currently on offer in
cognitive science and that “explicit representations of behaviour of knowledge
have no place in embodied solutions.”
Pierre
Steiner’s article in ‘Pragmatics and Cognition’ (2010) criticises the
representationalist assumptions that pertain to contemporary models of
cognition. He proposes that extended and distributed models of cognition should
reject representationalism, suggesting that their adherence to such a model
is a by-product of the extended character of science. Steiner is a philosopher,
with a particular interest in non-representationalism nestled in the broader
setting of mind and language.
This
idea is further examined by Anthony Chemero in his article ‘Anti-
Representationalism and the Dynamical Stance’ (2000). He aims to fill what he
sees as gaps in the arguments in favour of non-representationalism in cognitive
science. He divides this non-representationalism into two: ontological and
epistemic, before debating the merits and disadvantages of each view. This
article, published in the journal ‘Philosophy of Science’, sets out some of the
arguments for and against different strands of non- representationalism within
the wider area of cognition. In his 2009 book “Radical Embodied Cognitive
Science” Chemero again takes up a pragmatist critique of representationalism.
In it he argues that cognition should be viewed in terms of agent-environment
dynamics rather than in terms of representation or computation.
A
prominent theorist working in the Analytic tradition of philosophy and
exploring different theories of mind is John Searle (1983, 1992). He too is
concerned with the so-called ‘mind-body problem’ and, like Ryle before him,
Searle is also the subject of much debate amongst academics. Dennis Sauvé
(2006) claims that Searle writes of a collection of non-representational mental
capacities that make intentionality possible. He examines the reasons for this
observation and Searle’s conclusion that an intentional state cannot come into
being without the existence of a ‘background’ (the underlying non-representational
biological processes). Furthermore, Ronald McIntyre (1984) notes that Searle is
part of a growing number of analytic philosophers who have taken an interest in
the work of phenomenologist, Edmund Husserl. He draws many parallels between
Searle and Husserl, most notably in his study of the former’s
representationalist approach to intentionality. McIntyre devotes a lot of time
to a discussion of ‘networks’ and ‘backgrounds’; terms used by Searle in his
explanation of intentional content, and highlights his apparent struggle to
separate the idea of a non-representational ‘background’ and a representational
‘intentional state’. Thus, whilst Searle’s work may not be particularly non-representational
in nature, the discussions surrounding it provide some interesting points to
consider, in particular surrounding the separation of representational and
non-representational theories of mind.
Like
Searle, Peter Hacker (2003) has a longstanding interest in the work of Ludwig
Wittgenstein who, like many philosophers of the early 20th Century
(Sartre being another prominent example) had no need for a representational
theory of mind. Hacker is highly critical of what he sees as widespread
conceptual confusion in the work of many contemporary neuroscientists and
philosophers, including Searle. In collaboration with neuroscientist Maxwell
Bennett, Hacker has written several books that attempt to show how the careless
use of concepts leads scientists and philosophers astray. Amongst the many
concepts that Hacker and Bennett analyse, “representation” is regarded as generating
particular confusion. They explain (with examples drawn from neuroscience) how
scientists commonly confuse ordinary language uses of the term with its more restricted technical usage.
Coming
from a phenomenological standpoint, Hubert L. Dreyfus (2002) provides an
evaluation of the arguments set forth in Merlau-Ponty’s “Phenomenology of
Perception” (1962), and proposes that the most basic forms of intelligent
behaviour can be described and explained without recourse to mind or brain
representations. Instead he suggests that the skills needed for the body to
connect to the world are stored not as representations, but as dispositions to
respond to the solicitations of situations in the world. Despite providing this
interesting and useful assessment of Merleau-Ponty, Dreyfus’ other work
interprets, in a fashion akin to Searle, the writings of Husserl to be rooted
firmly in the representational tradition (1984). He even goes so far as to
describe Husserl’s theories as being in line with those of Jerry Fodor.
However, a number of papers and books are available that debate this, most
notably those by Beth Preston (1994) and Christian Lotz (2007). Preston argues
that Dreyfus should be seen as being at odds with the representational theory
of mind. She remarks that the relationship between Dreyfus and Fodor needs to
be re-examined, as well as the entire relationship between phenomenology and
what she describes as the Anglo-American philosophy of mind. This defence of
Husserl and subsequent criticism of Dreyfus is further explored in Lotz’s more
recent paper.
Like
Dreyfus, Varela, Thompson and Rorsch are clearly influenced by Merleau-Ponty in
their 1991 book “The Embodied Mind” which disavows representationalism in
favour of a situated, embodied and enactive theory. Shaun Gallagher and Dan
Zahavi (2008) take a similarly enactive view, as does Richard Mennary (2007) in
his book “Cognitive Integration: Mind and Cognition Unbounded”. Mennary argues
that in the study of mind, the units of interest are often too narrowly
restricted and he thus advocates a more extended and world involving
conception.
AlvaNoë’s “actional” theory (2004) is another prominent extended philosophy that
borrows to some degree from in Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology (in fact Noë was a
student of Dreyfus). Noë denies “internal representation” yet he evidently sees
no contradiction in his frequent reference to perceptual “content”. In contrast, Hutto and Myin (2013) are very critical of what is sometimes known as
the “content view”. They take a more radical position and argue that content
(i.e. representation) is limited to minds involved in “scaffolded” cultural
practices.
Like
Hutto and Myin, Mark H. Bickhard (1993) rejects the content view and raises
some very significant logical challenges for representationalism. He
explores a version of what has come to be known as the “Symbol Grounding
Problem” (Harnad 1990) in order to critique what he terms “encodingism”: the
mistaken assumption that intelligent processes necessarily involve
representations.
On several seperate occasions Kevin O’Regan (2011) has collaborated with Alva Noë and Eric Myin and
his approach obviously shares much in common with these two theorists. In
recent years he has further developed his sensorimotor theory of embodied and extended
cognition in which our manipulation of the environment is a central feature of
perception.
Another
contemporary paper comes from Alex Morgan (2013) who builds his argument around
the theories put forward by William Ramsey (2007). Ramsey agrees with the
structural conception of mental representation, yet uses it to develop an
argument against representationalism. From here, Morgan explores the idea that
although structural representations might count as genuine representations,
they aren’t distinctively mental representations, as they can be found in a
number of non-intentional systems.
Karim
Zahidi (2013) argues that non-representational cognitive science is a
relatively new paradigm in the study of cognition, that illustrates a radical departure
from classical cognitive science. In a similar way to the work of Miller,
Zahidi shows how one can develop a form of realism that reflects rather than
accommodates the core principles of non-representationalist embodied cognitive
science.
These
books and articles suggest that non-representational theories are of growing
interest and importance within both psychology and the philosophy of mind.
Whilst this review is neither extensive nor detailed, it is intended to highlight
the major theorists in the field, alongside some of the academics discussing
their work in current publications.
Bibliography:
BENNETT, M.R. AND HACKER, P.M.S., 2003.
Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. UK: Blackwell Publishing.
BICKHARD, M.H., 1993. Representational
content in humans and machines.Journal of Experimental & Theoretical
Artificial Intelligence, 5(4), pp.285-333.
CHARLES, E.P. ed., 2011. A new look
at New Realism: The psychology and philosophy of EB Holt (Vol. 1).
Transaction Publishers.
CHEMERO,
A., 2000. Anti-representationalism and the dynamical stance. Philosophy of Science, 67(4), pp. 625-647
CHEMERO,
A., 2009. Radical Embodied Cognitive
Science. MIT press.
CLARK,
A. and TORIBIO, J., 1994. Doing without representing? Synthese,
101(3), pp. 401-431
DREYFUS,
H.L., 2002. Intelligence without Representation. Phenomenology
and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(4), pp. 367-386
GALLAGHER, S. AND
ZAHAVI, D., 2002. The Phenomenological Mind
HARNAD,
S. (1990) The Symbol Grounding Problem. Physica D 42: 335-346.
HUTTO,
D. AND MYIN, E., 2013, Radical
Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content.
LOTZ,
C., 2007. Cognitivism and practical intentionality: A critique of Dreyfus's
critique of Husserl. International Philosophical
Quarterly, 47(2), pp. 153-166
MANDELBAUM,
M., 1958. Ryle and Psychology. Philosophical Review, 67(4), pp. 522-530
MASÍS,
J., 2012. Phenomenological skillful coping: Another counter-argument to Daniel
Dennett’s. Journal of Philosophy of Life, 2(1), pp. 67-91
MATTENS,
F., 2010. Philosophy and 'Experience' - A conflict of interests? Philosophy, Phenomenology, Sciences. Springer.
pp. 405-438
MCINTYRE,
RONALD, 1984. Searle on Intentionality. Inquiry,
27, pp. 468-483
MORGAN,
A., 2013. Representations gone mental. Synthese. [Online] Available from: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs11229-013-0328-7
[Accessed 2 June 2016]
NOË, A., 2004. Action in perception.
MIT press.
O’REGAN, J.K., 2011. Why red doesnt sound like a bell:
Understanding the feel of consciousness. Oxford University Press.
PRESTON,
B., 1994. Husserl’s non-representational theory of mind. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 32(2),
pp. 209-232
PRESTON,
B., 2012. A
Philosophy of Material Culture: Action, Function and Mind
RAMSEY,
W.M., 2007. Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
RYLE,
G., 1949. The concept of mind. Chicago:
Chicago University Press.
SAUVE,
D., 2006. Intentionality background according to John Searle. Dialogue- Canadian Philosophical Review, 45(1),
pp. 3-27
MAURICE
MERLEAU-PONTY, 1962. Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
SEARLE,
J., 1983. Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of
mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
SEARLE,
J., 1992. The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The MIT Press.
SHARON,
B., 1993. The representational and the presentational: An
essay on cognition and the study of mind. Hertfordshire:
Harvester Wheatsheaf.
SMALL,
R., 1981. Ryle and Husserl. Journal of the British Society
for Phenomenology, 12(3), pp. 195-211
SOLYMOSI, T., 2013. “Against Representation:
A Brief Introduction to Cultural Affordances,” Human Affairs 23(4): 594–605.
SOLYMOSI, TIBOR. Neuroscience,
Neurophilosophy and Pragmatism: Brains at Work with the World. Palgrave
Macmillan, 2014.
SORENSEN,
E., 2012. The mind and distributed cognition: The place of knowing in a maths
class. Theory & Psychology, 22(6), pp. 717-737
STEINER,
P., 2010. The bounds of representation: A non-representationalist use of the resources
of the model of extended cognition. Pragmatics &
Cognition, 18(2), pp. 235-272
VARELA, F.J. THOMPSON, E., & ROSCH, E.
1991. The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience.
WHEELER,
M., 2001. Two Threats to Representation. Synthese,
129(2), pp. 211- 231
Wilson, A.D. and Golonka, S., 2013. Embodied
cognition is not what you think it is. Front. Psychol., 12 February 2013 | http://dx.doi.org/10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00058 [Accessed 2 June 2016]
ZAHIDI,
K., 2013. Non-representationalist cognitive science and realism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences.
[Online] Available from: http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs11097-013-9310-6
[Accessed 2 June 2016]
0 comments:
Post a Comment